http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/cgi-bin/ptext?doc=Perseus%3Atext%3A1999.04.0009&query=toc&layout=&loc=1
Plato employed his theory of Forms
not only in metaphysical speculation about the original creation of the everyday
world in which people live but also in showing the way human society should be
constructed in an ideal world. One version of Plato's utopian vision is
found in his most famous dialogue, the Republic . This work, whose Greek
title (Politeia)
would be more accurately rendered as System of Government, primarily
concerns the nature of justice and the reasons that people should be just
instead of unjust. Justice,
Plato
argues, is advantageous; it consists of subordinating the irrational to the
rational in the soul. [Compare this to the
greater and lesser jihad in Islam.] By
using the truly just polis as a model for understanding this notion of proper
subordination in the soul, Plato
presents a vision of the ideal structure for human society.
Like a just soul, the just society would have its parts in proper hierarchy,
parts that Plato
in the Republic presents as three classes of people, as distinguished
by their ability to grasp the truth of Forms. The highest class
constitutes the rulers, or “guardians”
[These are the golden people who are driven by
intellect] as Plato
calls them, who are
educated in mathematics, astronomy, and metaphysics. Next come the “auxiliaries,” [These are the silver people who are driven by spirit] whose
function it is to defend the polis. [To this end, they are trained in gymnastics, mathematics,
music, etc.] The lowest class is that of the producers, [These are the iron class who are driven by appetite] who
grow the food and make the objects required by the whole population. [Their education comes from practical life experience and
early schooling.] Each
part contributes to society by fulfilling its proper function. [Plato theorizes
that by letting each person follow their own nature and arête, the society will
naturally find harmony and balance.]
Women as well as men qualify to be
guardians because they possess the same
virtues and abilities as men, except for a disparity in physical strength
between the average woman and the average man. The axiom justifying the
inclusion of women, namely that virtue is the same in women as in men,
is perhaps a notion that Plato
derived from Socrates.
The inclusion of women in the ruling class of Plato's utopian city-state
represented a startling
departure from the actual practice of his times. Indeed, never before in
Western history had anyone proposed-- even in fantasy-- that work be allocated
in human society without regard to gender. [Except for
Egypt, of course. Many people, it
seems, don’t consider Egypt a part of Western history or culture, though I see
many of the seeds of much Western thought and innovation harkening back to
ancient Egypt.] Moreover, to minimize distraction, guardians
are to have neither private property nor nuclear families. Male and
female guardians are to live in houses shared in common, to eat in the same
mess halls, and to exercise in the same gymnasiums. The children are to be
raised as a group in a common environment by special caretakers. [In Plato’s ideal daycare, the children would be exposed
exclusively to “the good” and would only be introduced to any corrupting
influence once they had completed their formative years.] Although this scheme is meant to free
women guardians from child-care responsibilities and enable them to rule
equally with men, Plato
fails to consider that women guardians would in reality have a much tougher
life than the men because they would have to be pregnant frequently and undergo
the strain and danger of giving birth. At the same time, he evidently does not
believe they are disqualified for ruling on this account. The guardians who achieved the
highest level of knowledge in Plato's ideal society would qualify to rule over
the ideally just state as philosopher-kings. [Philosopher-rulers were denied nuclear
families and were expected to complete in excess of fifty years of intense
education and training before taking the helm.
What benefit would this stipulation have? Why do you think guardians were disallowed nuclear families? Why do you think Plato believed the village
should raise the child? How do you
think Plato would feel about censorship in his utopia?]
To become a guardian, a person from childhood must be
educated for many years in mathematics, astronomy, and metaphysics to gain the
knowledge that Plato
in the Republic presented as necessary if one was to rule for the common
good. Plato's specifications for the education of guardians in fact make him
the first thinker to argue systematically that education should be the training
of the mind and the character rather than simply the acquisition of information
and practical skills. Such a state would necessarily be authoritarian
because only the ruling class would possess the knowledge to determine its
policies and make decisions determining who is allowed to mate with whom to
produce the best children. [As reasonable as this may
have seemed to Plato, eugenics has since become notorious because of Hitler’s
similar views on the subject and the resultant atrocities born of this
ideology.]
Plato
refused to accept the relativity of the virtues as reality. He developed the
theory that the virtues cannot be discovered through experience; rather, the
virtues are absolutes that can be apprehended only by thought and that somehow
exist independently of human existence.
(The sophists believed that virtue depended in
large part to circumstances and that morality and truth are relative for the
most part.) The separate realities of the pure virtues Plato
referred to in some of his works as Forms
(sing. eidos , plur. eide , or sing. idea , plur. ideai ); among the
Forms were Goodness,
Justice, Beauty, and Equality. He argued that the Forms were invisible,
invariable, and eternal entities located in a higher realm beyond the empirical
world of human beings. The Forms such as Goodness, Justice, Beauty, and
Equality are, according to Plato,
true reality; what humans
experience with their senses are the impure shadows of this reality.
Each Form, Plato
seems to say, is an essential quality, one that people experience only through
contrast between opposites. For example, that a stick embodies equality to
another of the same length but inequality to a stick of a different length
demonstrates equality only through contrast with the unequal stick. The Form
Equality, however, is the pure
essence of equality, which under no circumstances can be unequal or
possess the quality of inequality. Such a pure Form is beyond human experience. The same
reasoning applies to the other virtues such as goodness or beauty or justice.
Plato's concept of Forms required the further belief that
knowledge of them came through the human soul, which must be immortal. When a
soul is incarnated in its current body, it brings with it knowledge of the
Forms. The soul then uses reason in argument and proof, not empirical
observation through the senses, to recollect its pre-existent knowledge.
Plato
was not consistent
throughout his career in his views on the nature or the significance of Forms,
and his later works seem quite divorced from the theory. [Plato lived to be a very old man, and as is usually the
case, the knowledge gained in his youth transmuted as he gained experience and
wisdom. The Greeks have two words for
wisdom: sophia and sophon. Sophon is the unshakable certainty possessed
by the young whereas sophia is the wisdom that is the marriage of knowledge and
experience.] Nevertheless, Forms provide a good example of both the
complexity and the wide range of Platonic thought. With his theory of Forms, Plato
made metaphysics a central issue for philosophers ever since.
Plato's idea that humans possessed immortal
souls distinct from their bodies established the concept of dualism, [a.k.a. psychophysical dualism, which another famous
philosopher, Rene Descartes, would capitalize on two millennia later]
positing a separation between spiritual and physical being. This notion of the separateness of soul and body
would play an influential role in later philosophical and religious thought. In
a dialogue written late in his life, Plato
said the pre-existing knowledge possessed by the immortal human soul is in
truth the knowledge known to the supreme deity. Plato
called this god the Demiurge (“craftsman”) because the deity used knowledge
of the Forms to craft the world of living beings from raw matter. [This parallels the Judeo-Christian God known as Jehovah or
Yahweh or simply YHWH. The Gnostics also
had a similar god, named Yaldaboath, who came into existence when Sophia, the
feminine element of the overarching deity, had a thought. This thought became a creator god who
thought he was the almighty because he didn’t know his origins. His name literally means, “He who knows not
from whence he came.”] According
to this doctrine of Plato,
a knowing, rational God created the world, and the world therefore has order. [The Greek word for order is cosmos. In Greek myth, order was born out of the
primordial chaos. Not coincidentally,
most, if not all, religions that posit a creator deity share this birth of order
from chaos as the initial act of creation.]
Furthermore, its beings have goals, as evidenced by animals
adapting to their environments in order to flourish. The Demiurge wanted to
reproduce in the material world the perfect order of the Forms, but the world
as crafted turned out not to be perfect because matter is necessarily
imperfect. Plato
suggested that the proper
goal for human beings is to seek perfect order and purity in their own souls by
making rational desires control their irrational desires. The latter
cause harm in various ways. The desire to drink wine to excess,
for example, is irrational because the drinker fails to consider the hangover
to come the next day. Those
who are governed by irrational desires thus fail to consider the future of both
body and soul. Finally, since the soul is immortal and the body is not, our
present, impure existence is only one passing phase in our cosmic existence.
Socrates's fate had a profound effect
on his most brilliant follower, Plato
(ca. 428 -348 B.C.), who even though an aristocrat nevertheless withdrew from
political life after 399 B.C. The condemnation of Socrates
had apparently convinced Plato
that citizens in a democracy were incapable of rising above narrow
self-interest to knowledge of any universal truth. In his works dealing with
the organization of society, Plato
bitterly rejected democracy as a justifiable system of government. Instead, he
sketched what he saw as the philosophical basis for ideal political and social
structures among human beings. His utopian vision had virtually no effect on
the actual politics of his time, and his attempts to advise Dionysius
II (ruled 367-344 B.C.), tyrant of Syracuse
in Sicily,
on how to rule as a true philosopher ended in utter failure. Otherwise we have
almost no evidence for the events of Plato's life.
Political philosophy formed only one
portion of Plato's interests, which ranged widely in astronomy, mathematics,
and metaphysics (theoretical explanations for phenomena that cannot be
understood through direct experience or scientific experiment). After Plato's
death, his ideas attracted relatively little attention among philosophers for
the next two centuries, until they were revived as important points for debate
in the Roman
era. Nevertheless, the sheer intellectual power of Plato's thought and the
controversy it has engendered ever since his lifetime have won him fame as one
of the world's greatest philosophers.
Plato's
views seem to have
changed over time, and he nowhere presents one, coherent set of doctrines.
Although it is unwise to try to summarize Plato
rather than to read his dialogues as complete pieces, it is perhaps not too misleading
to say that he taught that
human beings cannot define and understand absolute virtues such as goodness,
justice, beauty, or equality by the concrete evidence of these qualities in
their lives. Any earthly examples will in another context display the opposite
quality. For instance, always returning what one has borrowed might seem to be
just. But what if a person who has borrowed a weapon from a friend is confronted
by that friend who wants the weapon back to commit a murder?
In this case, returning the borrowed item would be unjust. Examples of equality are also only relative.
The equality of a stick two feet long, for example, is evident when it is
compared with another two-foot stick. Paired with a three-foot stick, however,
it displays inequality. In sum, in the world that human beings experience with their senses, every
example of the virtues and every quality is relative in some aspect of its
context.